Analysis of Wealth. II. Surplus Value

In a former article under this heading the writer tried to show that the substance of value, the common property of all commodities as such, is social labour, measured by the time taken in its expenditure. He tried to show further that money serves as a measure of values, a standard of prices, and a medium of circulation, only because it is itself a commodity, that is to say, it embodies social labour in the same manner as do the articles for which it is exchanged. He tried to show still further that the production of commodities, i.e., articles for exchange, and the use of money are features of a certain stage of development in the means and methods of production and in the control thereof, and are destined to disappear with future progress.

We have now to consider money a little further in the form of capital in the process of accumulation, or in other words, the phenomenon of “money making money.” For money in itself is not necessarily capital. Only when it is used for the purpose of adding to itself does it become so. When the independent producer (peasant or handicraftsman) brought his goods to market he received for them a certain sum of money which sooner or later he expended on articles of a different sort, largely for his own personal use and partly, of course, to buy fresh raw material, etc. To him the money entering transiently into his possession was not capital. Nor were the goods he sold, for he received in exchange goods of equal value. No interest, no profit, accrued to him in the transaction.

Otherwise is it with the modern capitalist with a sum of money, which is constantly expanding in volume. He buys commodities not for consumption by himself, but in order that in some form or other he may re-sell these commodities and realise a profit on the transac­tion. Apart from this profit his activities as a capitalist would be meaningless.

The independent producer bought commodi­ties mainly in order to realise their use-value in his own person. The capitalist buys them only to throw them back into circulation and receive in return an increase in exchange-value. The simplest definition of capital, then, is money thrown into circulation only to be received back again with an increase to itself, which increase becomes part of the capital which is again advanced to return with a fresh increase.

This increase or profit Marx calls surplus-value. The problem of its origin is the central one in economic science, and its solution holds the key to an understanding of all the workings of capitalism.

The quest for profit is the mainspring of the present social order. Let us take the mainspring out of the case and examine it.

In the first place, it is obvious that money must go into circulation in order to increase itself. If it simply lay in a safe it would remain the same in quantity. Thus is the modern capitalist cuter than the old-fashioned miser. Being a “true Christian” he refrains from the stupid, worthless process of hugging his money to himself, and lets it go believing implicitly in the words of his Lord : “Whosoever would save his life the same shall lose it, but whosoever loseth his life for my sake [“profits’] the same shall find it.” But bearing in mind that on the average prices are determined by values, and these latter by the socially necessary labour embodied in commodities, it is also clear that the circulation of money cannot in itself give rise to profit. On the average the capitalist buys commodities at their values and sells them again at their values. He exchanges equivalents, and unless some increase of value takes place between the two acts of buying and selling he can realise no profit. Various orthodox theories have tried to see the origin of surplus value in the process of exchange. The investigation of these theories, however, shows them to be based either upon the confusion of use-value with exchange-value or upon the illusion that prices (and implicitly values) are determined by the arbitrary will of the owner of commodities or by mere chance.

In dealing with capital the scientific economist is concerned not with an accumulation of use-values, but of exchange-value in the form of money ; which accumulation, moreover, is not made by one or a few capitalists at the expense of the rest, but by the capitalist class as a whole. Ihe origin of surplus-value is, therefore, to be found in production, or in other words, in the productive consumption of the commodities originally purchased.

All commodities which are consumed in order to re-appear as new commodities may be said to be productively consumed. For instance, leather purchased by a boot manufacturer is consumed in the factory to reappear as boots. The boots, moreover, contain more value than the leather, since they embody additional labour. This additional value, however, is by no means necessarily surplus-value. Imagine, for instance, an independent boot-maker purchasing his own tools and raw materials and selling his own product. The value of the raw materials, etc., is transmitted to the finished product, which, in addition, contains the value added by the bootmaker’s labour. The boots are sold for more money than was paid for the leather and the tools, but no surplus-value has been realised ; money does not in this instance make money. The raw materials, etc., do not transmit more value than they themselves contain ; all the increase is due to the boot-maker’s labour. The difference between the original outlay and the price he gets for his commodity is simply equal to the value he has added. The effect is the same as if he had made no outlay but produced a new and distinct commodity and sold it. His money has not expanded itself ; he has simply added to it. In short, it is not capital. Men do not become capitalists and wealthy in the modern sense by themselves adding value to natural objects. Rather, the increase of their wealth is obviously independent of their efforts and totally out of proportion to any they might make.

Nevertheless, seeing that all value is but the embodiment of labour, surplus-value, being a particular form of value, can only be derived from labouring in some fashion. Therefore in order to obtain surplus-value the capitalist must find in the market not merely ordinary commodities (which are in capable of producing for him more value than they themeslves possess) but some commodity which actually produces value, i.e., labours. This commodity he finds in the energies of the modern wage-labourer. It matters little to the capitalist what other commodities he deals in. Food or clothing, luxuries or necessities, all alike embody labour, therefore it is the labouring commodity which he essentially requires in order to obtain profit.

When the capitalist purchases other commodities he buys congealed labour : labour which is past, dead, inactive. From them alone he can expect no increase of value. In buying labour-power, however, he secures the potential source of all further value. So far as he is concerned the special function of labour-power is to pro­duce value and, above all, surplus-value. With the usefulness of labour-power, in any other sense he is not concerned, any more than he is concerned with the utility of the goods he sells. Capital being but a sum of exchange-values, its sole passion is for its own growth by the pro­duction of more exchange-value, which means the continual consumption of labour-power. It remains to show how by this consumption surplus-value is actually produced.

Labour-power, like every other commodity, possess an exchange-value, which is realised in a price, termed wages. The amount of this exchange-value is determined by the labour-time spent in its production. The average wages of any section of the working class depends upon the cost of its customary necessities of life, including such special education as may be necessary in the branch of industry in which it is employed. It is obvious that wages cannot be long depressed below this standard without impairing the productive efficiency of the labourers’ energies. On the other hand, if they rise far above this standard the surplus-value is encroached upon. For surplus-value is nothing more than the difference between the wages of the labourers and the sum total value of their product. Were the labourers in the habit of producing no more wealth than would keep them, in working condition surplus-value would be impossible. The labour market, like the market for other commodities, is liable to fluctuations, but experience shows that these cancel one another, and that the general level of wages is such as will maintain the workers in their daily tasks.

But though the price of labour-power is limited in this way, the limit of surplus-value is simply the productivity of labour-power. Anyone purchasing a conmodity acquires the use of it, and the capitalist only buys labour-power in order that he may use it up, i.e., set it to produce the greatest possible amount of exchange-value in the form of commodities. Here we may take examples from Marx (“Capital,” Vol. I. p. 106).

Marx first supposes a capitalist advancing a sum of 15s. which is split up as follows : 10s, is the price of 10 lbs. of cotton ; 2s. represents the value of wear and tear of machinery, etc.; 3s. is paid for the hire of labour-power. We have thus a sum of 12s. as constant capital, i.e., value which passes unchanged into the form of the finished product, yarn. This is assumed to be the product of two days labour of twelve hours each, i.e., two hours labour is embodied in a sum of 1s., or a commodity of that value. Supposing now that in six hours the 10 lbs of cotton are converted into 10 lbs of yarn, The yarn contains thirty hours labour ; twenty-four being spent in producing raw material, etc., and six in converting it into finished product. Its value,, therefore, is 15s., i.e., 1s.for every two hours labour.

Here no surplus-value is created, for 15s. was the sum originally advanced. By only working six hours the labourer has done no more than produce an equivalent of his wages, 3s., and the capitalist makes no profit.

Marx now gives a second case. In this the capitalist advances 27s. Twenty lbs. of cotton are bought for 20s., and 4s. is allowed for wear and tear. The labourer is paid his wages of 3s., but instead of working only six hours is made to work twelve, having exactly twice the amount of raw material to convert into yarn. This time the yarn represents 60 hours labour, 48 being contained in raw material and twelve being added in the process of spinning. If 30 hours labour are represented by 15s., then 60 hours are embodied in 30s.

The capital advanced was 27s., so that the capitalist makes a profit of 3s. when selling the goods in the market at their value.

These simple examples illustrate the whole character of capitalist production. Carried on as it may be with all due regard to legal forms, it yet consists of a process of robbery disguised by the exchange of equal values.

The capitalist certainly gives the labourer his “due,” i.e., the value of his energies, or in other words, the cost of production of his commodity labour-power, but if the labourer simply replaced this value the capitalist would gain nothing. For him the transaction is meaningless unless the worker produces far more than that, unless, in fact, his whole life-time becomes but a process of producing value.

In further articles the writer hopes to outline how capital in its lust for self-expansion pushes the exhaustion of labour-power to its limits. For the present it is as well to remember the cause of the subjection of labour-power to capital.

The worker sells himself (in the form of his energies) as a commodity. Why ? His obvious motive is to obtain his price, wages. These as we see, however, only represent sufficient to keep him in existence. It follows, then, that he lacks the means of subsistence and must purchase them, which still further implies that he does not possess the wherewithal to produce them. This is another point to be dealt with later.

E.B.

Leave a Reply